Fordham


IHSP

Medieval History


Selected Sources Full Text Sources Saints' Lives Law Texts Maps Medieval Films Search Help


Selected Sources Sections Studying History End of Rome Byzantium Islam Roman Church Early Germans Anglo-Saxons Celtic World Carolingians 10 C Collapse Economic Life Crusades Empire & Papacy France England Celtic States Nordic Europe Iberia Italy Eastern Europe Intellectual Life Medieval Church Jewish Life Social History Sex & Gender States & Society Renaissance Reformation Exploration
IHSP Credits
Medieval Sourcebook:
Two Reviews of Susan Reynolds: Fiefs and Vassels (1994)


Fred Cheyette

SUSAN REYNOLDS, Fiefs and Vassals: The Medieval Evidence Reinterpreted. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994. Pp. xi, 544. $29.95.

Susan Reynolds must have received with dismay or resigned disbelief the Medieval Academy's announcement that by popular demand the next volume to appear in the MART series would be Francois Ganshof's Feudalism, for this, her most recent book, already widely reviewed, is nearly five hundred pages of vigorously argued anti-Ganshof. Attacking Ganshof's "classic" and clearly still-admired work is, of course, not new; it was a commonplace in conference hallway conversation when I was barely out of graduate school, and Elizabeth Brown (to whom Reynolds dedicates this work) led the way in print over twenty years ago in a wide-ranging and sharply pointed article in the American Historical Review.1 Until Reynolds, however, no one has tried to grind systematically through the sources on which that conventional (non-Marxist) construction of "feudalism" has been based to see whether they will bear the weight. Nor has anyone in many years looked closely at the twelfth-century Libri feudorum, which Brown already pointed to as the fons et origo of the modern concept of feudalism. Now Reynolds has done both, missing (with regret) only the Hispanic peninsula in her sweep through the library stacks. Her conclusion is that the ism is built on sand, that the documents interpreted by generations of medievalists as representing "feudal" forms of landholding and "feudal" relations of vassals and lords will do so only if forced, only if one reads them with the assumption that that is what they must do. Without that assumption, she argues, they can be read to say very different things; and indeed many texts can be read through the lens of conventional "feudalism" only by doing them violence.

Because Reynolds covers such vast territories, even without the medieval Spains, this is a very complex book, and the relentlessly argumentative style in which she carries on her discussions with a century of medievalists will probably put off many readers. One often has the impression of listening to half of a heated telephone conversation, knowing you could discover the other half by following out the footnotes, and learn what exactly is being argued about by reading the documents to which those footnotes lead, but wanting the time or ambition or even the access to the well-stocked research library that such further reading would require. If the tone and style get in the way of the contents it would be unfortunate, for Reynolds's ambition is nothing less than to change the way historians of medieval European society and politics (and to a certain extent of literature as well) do their work, the way they read their documents, the way they understand what the words that pass before their eyes imply. And her arguments must be taken seriously. If she is successful, certain assumptions will no longer hold easy sway, and post-Reynolds accounts of European society in the half millennium from Charlemagne to 1300 will differ in significant ways from the pre-Reynolds accounts that she criticizes.

Reynolds, following Ganshof (and many others), condenses "feudalism" to two concepts (distinguishing carefully, as she tries to do throughout, between words, concepts, and phenomena): vassalage and fiefs. The first she dismisses in one short chapter, concluding that "vassalage. . . is a term that no longer matches either the evidence we have available or the conceptual tools we need to use in analyzing it. It is both too diffuse and too narrow -- not surprisingly, since it survives from a primitive stage of the study of social relations. . . . Vassalage is too vacuous a concept to be useful" (p. 47). The remainder of the book is then devoted to fiefs, whatever they may have been called in medieval Latin or in the various vernaculars, and far more generally to "the rights and obligations of property." This is the heart of her work. Piloted by the numerous historians who have written about medieval property or analyzed medieval charters, Reynolds has "trawled" (her metaphor) the farthest recesses of the British Library, using gill nets that stretch for miles; she has worked enough fishing banks to put mere archive anglers, such as myself, to shame. Going country by country and century by century to the printed sources, she asks, in effect, If I don't assume in advance that there was such a thing as feudalism and that the words fevum, beneficium,casamentum, and their equivalents have a specific technical meaning (such as the one given by Ganshof), that is, if I make no a priori assumptions about the words used in these documents, what do they tell me about the rights and obligations of property?

It will take years to unpack the holds Reynolds has filled with her catch to see how much is really fit to be served up and how much had best be thrown back in the sea. There are more than enough individual hypotheses and particular readings here to keep a legion of seminars and dissertation writers going for a generation. No reviewer unwilling to spend years fishing these same banks can give more than a modest and very partial assessment of the individual source readings that make up the bulk of her work. Those she has found in collections from Occitania, my own narrow range of expertise, she reads in a limited and sometimes strange manner (I will discuss one example later), but, in my view, a more exact reading of those texts would strengthen rather than weaken her argument. Reynolds does not twist the texts to conform to her purpose; she has simply read them too rapidly. Given the vast reach of this book, one may suspect that this is more than occasionally the case; but whether that invalidates her argument only detailed and more exacting research will tell.

In the meantime, it is not such painstaking text-by-text readings that should command the attention of historians, but rather the larger arguments that run in the background while all the detail work occupies the screen. Three seem to me of particular importance. The first is methodological: it is about how the words in the texts we use as evidence are to be interpreted. This argument has the greatest potential to make us uneasy about our traditional manner of reading charter evidence. The second argument is historiographical: it asserts that we have been imprisoned by a centuries-old interpretive tradition and asks us by implication where else in our constructions of medieval society we have been so imprisoned. It also demands an alternative construction, whose elements Reynolds tries to supply (with but partial success, in my view). In particular, it focuses our attention on the changes that twelfth- and thirteenth-century rulers were bringing about in the way they exercised authority and the way that professional jurists helped shape those changes, and asks us to reconsider radically the relationship of what came after those changes to what came before. The third argument is anthropological and philosophical: it concerns the meaning and nature of law and government as features of social structure. I shall take these up in order.

The methodological issue is everywhere implicit in Reynolds's argument. Those who read medieval documents through the lenses of the conventional construction of "feudalism" make two fundamental assumptions: first that the documents, especially charters, are legal documents, drawing their meaning from a preexisting body of law, be it Roman (Theodosian, Visigothic, Justinianic), ecclesiastical, or customary; second -- a corollary of the first -- that particular words in those documents have technical meanings which they retain over long periods of time, meanings given to them by that body of law. For "feudalism" (and thus for Reynolds's argument) the critical words are nouns that refer to property, such as proprietas, alod, feudum, casamentum, beneficium, honor, and verbs, such as tenere, associated with them, as well as expressions such as auxilium et consilium, cavalcatum, and others that express obligations. The very structure of Ganshof's little book depends on these assumptions; Annales social history in the wake of Georges Duby's Mâconnais (at which Reynolds levels a stringent critique, pp. 166-67) would not exist without them; they have their most vocal contemporary defenders in such French historians as Elisabeth Magnou-Nortier, Jean-Pierre Poly, and Eric Bournazel. This suggests the stakes on the table.

To these assumptions Reynolds responds with a radical nominalism. Sometimes it takes an extreme form: "Abstract nouns like feo, fevum, feudum. . . cannot be assumed to have has consistent meanings outside their contexts. Even if one context suggests some content for a word, that content cannot be assumed to be inherent in the word itself in such a way as to be transferred to other contexts and other cases. Contexts, unfortunately, are often unhelpful in this period [900-1100]. . . . Scribes may have used apparently classificatory nouns to describe pieces of property without being concerned to distinguish anything we might call different and definable categories of property" (pp. 119-20). Taken at face value, this turns eleventh-century scribes into the Humpty Dumpty of Alice through the Looking Glass, "When I use a word. . . it means just what I choose it to mean -- neither more nor less." Other occasions, happily, prove that this is just a (not uncommon) example of Reynolds's loose talk. What she really means most of the time is what she asserts later in the same paragraph: "Even if [the scribes] were interested in distinctions, the words used in records. . . could not have had the technical senses they might acquire in later ages of professional law." Sometimes, as in this particular argument, Reynolds asserts that meanings may have varied from monastery to monastery; at other moments the argument seems to be that they varied from region to region and even in the same community or region may have varied significantly over time.

Professionals (if not undergraduates) have long abandoned the quaint notion of "the medieval mind." Reynolds seems to urge us to push that skeptical recognition of regional and temporal differences to its farthest extreme, to the point where it seems to undermine the very possibility of language's acting as a vehicle for meaning. Yet she is convinced she knows what words do not mean, without apparently seeing the logical box she thus puts herself in. In the end, the theory seems less important to her than the practical result she is striving after: to undo our confidence in our ability to interpret early charters securely by merely referring to Du Cange or Niermeyer, or, far worse, by referring to legal history textbooks or reading the thirteenth or fourteenth century back into the eleventh or northern French or English practice into Italy or Germany.

One need not go to Reynolds's nominalist extreme to recognize the importance of her critique. How many times does one see a historian using the simple word feudum in a text, or the presence of a lord approving an alienation, or the notation that a piece of land or a right was "held of" someone as a justification to extrapolate into the world of that text a complex of obligations and relationships of subordination, or -- a leap of reasoning Reynolds does not canvas, but which is of the same order -- using a charter that states A gives a piece of land or rights to B to assert that A somehow possessed what he or she was giving, the historian then spinning out some scenario to put that land in A's hands in order for it to be given away. In an article published in this journal in 1988 I showed how mistaken that second move could be; in the eleventh century the common forms of conveyance -- sale, gift, mortgage, etc. -- did not necessarily carry the implications that they did in ancient Rome or do in the modern world; we impute such contents to them at our peril. If such simple and straightforward words as "sell," "give," and "grant" did not have technical meanings on which we can unfailingly depend, should we not also be wary of words like "alod" and "fief"?

Being wary, however, can be a road to paralyzing skepticism of the sort implied in Reynolds's most extreme formulations. How can we save ourselves from being forced to renounce the possibility of knowledge? Traditional lexicography assumes a fixed meaning or set of meanings for words (and assuming words to be "legal" pins those meanings down even more exactly). Here, however, we seem to face not a plurality but a fluidity of possible meanings. How then can we interpret what we read? Beyond the general exhortation to "look at the context," Reynolds is not much help. What context? What should we mean by "meaning"?

Traditional lexicography finds what it looks for by comparing texts; it assumes that words share common meanings across texts. This has been the method employed by Annales social history to interpret medieval charters; it is what gives many of those works their strikingly "institutional" air. An alternative (whose possibilities would have sent many of the arguments in this book in a very different direction) has been richly explored by Barbara Rosenwein and Stephen D. White when they have asked of their eleventh-century Burgundian and Loire valley charters, What are the particular ongoing social relationships to which these documents testify?2 When they ask, that is, what people are doing rather than what is the nature of legal institutions or social classes. Perhaps this is what Reynolds means by "context," but if so, she does not make it clear or draw the consequences, the most important of which would be to question her own premises in writing this book: that the critical issue is defining property rights and the connection of words to rights, rather than looking at the dynamics of human relations and asking to what extent and in what ways the documents that survive represent or structure those relations.

For Reynolds, the problem of what words like feudum, beneficium, and alod mean is part of a larger problem: the source of "feudalism" itself as a historiographical concept. "Fiefs and vassalage are post-medieval constructs, though rather earlier than the construct of feudalism. . . . Even when historians follow the terminology of their documents. . . they tend to fit their findings into a framework of interpretation that was devised in the sixteenth century and elaborated in the seventeenth and eighteenth. . . We cannot understand medieval society and its property relations if we see it through seventeenth- or eighteenth century spectacles" (pp. 2-3). Reynolds goes on to argue that the academic law of fiefs was the creation of the later Middle Ages and of bureaucratic, professionalized governments and, as "expert law," did not develop out of the customary law of noble property of an earlier age; whatever connections it had to practices of an earlier age, she adds, was to the relations of bishops and abbots to their tenants rather then of great secular lords to theirs.

Reynolds does not, to be sure, always stick with this chronology: at one moment she suggests that learned lawyers may have influenced practice in Montpellier at the beginning of the twelfth century; at others she is certain she has found such influences in the later twelfth or early thirteenth centuries, though the arguments she presents are largely hypothetical and her sentences liberally sprinkled with the auxiliary verb "may" -- again presenting a rich lode for future seminar-paper writers.

The chronological issue, however, is only part of the problem.

Let us assume that Reynolds is correct in asserting that a "law of fiefs," or more exactly "laws of fiefs," developed in the later Middle Ages in various European venues, and that -- outside of England -- such laws were profoundly shaped by academic law, especially from the texts and commentaries on the Libri feudorum. This is not a priori an unlikely scenario. The Libri quickly became part of the roman law studied in the universities, and, from the fourteenth century on, the case law developed in the Parlement of Paris, for example, was profoundly influenced by academic laws, with pleaders regularly appealing to texts they had learned on school benches to support their arguments. It would be surprising if this was not the case elsewhere on the Continent as well. Suppose then that we find appeals to such academic laws of fiefs in the records. Would this not raise the question why such rules and practices were allowed to shape court decisions? Should we follow the school of judicial "Realism" so popular in America earlier in this century and say that, in the later Middle Ages as well, the law was whatever judges said it was, assume that they and the advocates who plied their trade in their courts could shape the law any way they saw fit? Would plaintiffs have chosen to litigate in those courts? Would royal lawyers have been able to impose a structure of property law that did not conform to some accepted notions of substantive right held, at the very least, by the propertied classes? We know what difficulties it caused when kings attempted to impulse other obligations and restrictions on their subjects' property through taxation, how lengthy and complex the negotiations had to be. In contrast, there were no revolts, no demands for concessions or charters of privilege in response to a wholesale introduction of new legal rules. The argument that property law was radically reshaped under the influence of academic law seems on its face to e unlikely. Whose interests would it have served?

How, then, was what became the "law(s) of fiefs" in the age of academically trained lawyers related to what came before? This is not one question but a whole complex of questions, and on them Reynolds's occasional brief comments shed little light. They are, however, by implication at the very center of her enterprise.

Traditional accounts of "feudalism" -- Bloch, Ganshof -- speak of "the joining of fief to vassalage" or "the reification of fidelity." Reynolds has no truck with either the expression s or the various chronologies given for this linkage (see esp. pp. 18-19, 92-93, 118-19). Yet eleventh-and twelfth-century documents that explicitly tie fidelity to property are not all that hard to find. Indeed, Reynolds discusses one group at length, as an example of what she takes to be the intrusion of professional law into the relations of secular lords and their subjects at the very beginning of the twelfth century. The documents are contained in the Liber instrumentorum memorialium of the lords of Montpellier, and Reynolds (pp. 260-65) reads them as the original nineteenth-century editor of the cartulary and everyone since has done, as conversion of alods into fiefs -- in French terminology as "fiefs de reprise."3

Strictly speaking these are groups of texts that all follow the same formula: one states that a donor gives his castle and village or other property "ad alodium" to William [V or VI] of Montpellier, usually getting money in return; a second states that William gives the same property to the donor "ad feudum"; a third records an oath of fidelity. (Sometimes the first two acts are rolled into one.) Reynolds has not noticed a strange property of a number of these donations, however: they include sometimes quite elaborate provisions regarding the succession to the lordship of Montpellier of the sort (to take the text involving the castle of Pignan in 1114) "if William [V] of Montpellier did not devise (dividebat) this castle [by will], then I give it to his eldest son; if his eldest son has died (moreretur) without heir, then I give it to his second son" (etc. with more detail following). What are we to make of this? It could be simply read as an attempt to assure the donor's continuing loyalty to the dynasty, a complement to the notation in the same document that William's wife has given forty solidi to the donor "for his love" (pro drudo). But another possibility behind this strange sequence of verbs (imperfect, present, imperfect, present, all clearly regarding future events, for William V did not die until 1121), aside from indicating the scribe's limited Latinity (and thus seriously questioning "academic" influence on this document), is that it makes explicit the expectation that on William V's death the donor would give the castle again to William's sons in the order of succession that William had already determined. That is, the gift "ad alodium" was not a once-for-all-time event; it was not conceived of as permanently transferring a "bundle of rights" from one person to another. The later gifts "ad alodium" by other members of the original donor's family, including his mother in 1139, were thus not gifts of different rights to Pignan but of the same rights as those contained in the first surviving donation, as different people took possession of them.

Evidence that this hypothesis is not purely fanciful can be found elsewhere in the same cartulary in the records for the castle of Poujet, for which a Girundes, daughter of Adivena, gave an oathe of fidelity in the later eleventh century; in 1124 three of her descendants, including another Girundes, sold "ad alodium" to William VI and received back "ad feudum" exactly the same rights their ancestor Girundes had held. For their share in the same castle, Adalais and her husband William Assalit gave oaths of fidelity in 1114 to William V and in 1127 to his second son, William of Aumelas; after her husband's death in 1132, Adalais sold her share "ad alodium" to William VI and received it back "ad feudum."4 Why, then, do we not have repeated donations or sales of the same castle joined to the repeated oaths of fidelity in this cartulary? Perhaps, in fact, we do but cannot recognize them because the genealogical connections among the donors or sellers are no longer recognizable. Another possibility is that the notary who assembled this cartulary early in the thirteenth century was not simply a mindless gatherer and copier of parchments lying around his office; he was already a historian, and his choice of what to include and what to omit was already an act of interpretation. He wa a school-trained lawyer; from the point of view of Roman law, repeated gifts made no sense, so, we might hypothesize, he copied the earliest surviving example and put aside the others.

When read closely, these documents and others like them impel us to go well beyond Reynolds's general critique of "feudalism." The practice of repeatedly giving "ad alodium" from generation to generation what is then repeatedly granted "ad feudum" indeed calls into question the distinction commonly made between "full property" and "fief"'; if the original donor has "full" rights, which he gives to his lord, who gives less than full rights back (for those rights are restricted at the very least by the oath of fidelity and the obligations it expresses), then there is something paradoxical in the original donor's heirs making an equivalent donation at the time they take up their inheritance. But the practice raises far more questions than that: it suggests that an analysis of the rights one or another individual might hold in the property is here simply beside the point. What seems to be important for the participants is the entire ritual of donation, return grant, and oath of fidelity, a ritual that served to implant a personal relationship, what the document from Pignan refers to as "love," into the landscape. The particular words that the scribe scratched on parchment were of less importance than the action and the words that were uttered. But Reynolds will have no part of this. While she admits that "interpersonal relations between powerful people. . . mattered" (p. 46), her entire chapter on "vassalage" is a sustained argument against placing such relations anywhere but on the periphery of our analysis of power and its operations.

I would not argue foe a moment that we should return to the conventional concept of vassalage to explain what is taking place in these documents form Montpellier, or to the conventional scenario of "the joining of fief to vassalage," for such legalistic concepts seem to drain the relations involved of much of their richness and complexity, to draw a veil over a world where a word like "love" can find its place in charters as well as in lyric poetry. Reynolds, one indeed could argue, is not radical enough in her critique of "feudalism." She has rejected the Ganshofian description of the rights and obligations associated with fiefs and vassalage, but she does not herself escape the analytical categories of rights and obligations associated with property. Yet the documents from Montpellier insistently push us outside of those categories, telling us that scribal words do not always correspond one-to-one with social processes.

What keeps Reynolds enclosed within these categories is the sharp distinction she insists upon between powers of government on the one hand and property on the other, the distinction at the heart of Enlightenment and nineteenth-century Liberal political theory. In her discussion of Eigenkirchenwesen, for example, she remarks, "There does not seem to be any reason to see control and interference as falling on the property side of the boundary between proprietary and governmental rights" (p. 61; see also pp. 418-19). Elsewhere she argues that the consent of lords to alienation of property implies rights of "political or governmental" nature rather than anything about land law, that jurisdiction is "an attribute of government rather than a right of property" (pp. 61, 163). Often she argues that a particular exercise of lordship looks like "what we would call government." "What rulers at any level had to do," she says of the Carolingians (p. 131), "was to make their subjects. . . acknowledge, in effect, that their property was held under government."

By her account, then, what people did with property must be analyzed separately from the way they acted "governmentally"; it is only the anachronistic application of "feudalism" that has led us to confuse the two. At times Reynolds identifies the "governmental" or "political" with "bureaucratic" or "institutional" (e.g., p. 26) as when Carolingian counts are termed "government employees" (p. 87); at other times government is "coercive domination" (p. 34) and the state "an organization. . . that more or less successfully claims the control (not the monopoly) of the legitimate use of physical force (p. 27).

Doesn't this modification of Max Weber's classic definition, however, beg all the interesting questions: Who makes the claim? What are the means of control? Does the absence of a claim to monopoly make an important difference? and, above all Who asserts and Who decides what is "legitimate" and what is not and on what grounds? Stephen D. White in his review of the book5 comments extensively on Reynolds's use of "government" and "political" as an analytical category; there is no need for me to go over the same ground. If we are asked to reject the essentially modern analytical categories of "feudalism," why should we be asked to accept without further discussion these other essentially modern categories? Reynolds seems to have forgotten that the distinction between property and government traveled a long and tortuous road in Western thought. One has only to read Charles I's speech from the scaffold in front of the Banqueting Hall to recall how tenacious the "confusion" of the two still was in the mid-seventeenth century.

That "confusion" goes far back into the Middle Ages. Even in a case law as academically informed as that of the fourteenth-century Parlement of Paris one would be hard put to find the "boundary" between government and property that Reynolds so easily discovers before the twelfth century. Jurisdictions, the right to tax and the right to be free of taxes, the right to summon men to military service and the right to be free of summons, even indeed the powers and jurisdictional rights of bishops -- in short all the sorts of activities that "we would call governmental" -- were litigated as property rights.6 In this both judges and litigators were only following the habits long entrenched in the practice of eleventh- and twelfth-century scribes and their employers, who made no distinction between vineyards, fields, castles, the right to hang thieves, and dominatio or districtus when they drew up charters: they were all property that could be sold, given, mortgaged, divided up in testaments, granted as dowries or marriage portions. It is exactly this "confusion" that makes the argument over the existence or nonexistence of a public/private distinction in the Middle Ages so difficult to resolve. for we are wont to place "governmental" activities in the public sphere and "property" in the private, and medieval practice did not.

In the creation of this distinction we hold to be so obvious, law and lawyers played a prominent part. It is one of the important contributions of Reynolds's volume to remind us of the great transformation they brought about in the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries, a transformation that has been somewhat lost from sight with the decline of traditional institutional history. Reynolds's work may serve as a wake-up cal to renew the questions we put to what in the pre-Dubian age was the central focus of much Anglo-American medieval history. At the same time, by implication, it reminds us how carefully we should consider what those questions ought to be. Just as she has projected "government" as an analytical category back into the centuries before 1200, so has she done with "customary law," even though that concept is also the creation of academic law. To Reynolds, the transformation is thus one from customary law to "professional, academic law" and bureaucracy.

This, of course, is of a piece with her concentration on the "rights and obligations" of property as distinct from "government." It seems worth asking, however, whether, or to what extent, pre-1200 society was ordered by abstract rules that we can call "customary law." Or do we find them there -- as Reynolds argues for "feudalism" -- only because we assume them to have existed? To the extent that they existed, to what extent were they thought about systematically? (Reynolds argues that they were not.) Were they rules that concerned property rights? Or did they concern such values as honor, family solidarity, status, fidelity, and love -- values whose realization had to be continually renegotiated and repeatedly exemplified and confirmed in rituals of exchange? If we focus our attention primarily on the property caught up in these exchanges, are we perhaps mistaking the secondary for the primary? And are rights and obligations attached to property, or are they instead an outcome of the ritual of exchange itself? Should we look for institutions abstracted from individuals, or should our research prey be, first, the individuals in their particular, complex networks of relationships and, second, the systematic practices and transactions in which they engaged?

These are all, I believe, important questions, and a less powerful and less daring work than Reynolds's would not have raised them. Thanks to her thoroughgoing critique of the conventional concept of "feudalism," historian will have to reconsider some of their most fundamental questions about the social structure and political organization of the central Middle Ages. Reynolds joins Jean Durliat and Dominque Barthélemy, among others, in shaking the foundations of what was once our confidently accepted common wisdom. We are clearly in for an exciting ride. Her book is one that everyone concerned with the period should read, reread, and ponder.

FREDERIC L. CHEYETTE, Amherst College

FOOTNOTES

1. E.A.R. Brown, "The Tyranny of a Construct: Feudalism and Historians of Medieval Europe," American Historical Review 79 (1974), 1063-88.

2. Barbara H. Rosenwein, To Be the Neighbor of Saint Peter: The Social Meaning of Cluny's Property, 909-1049 (Ithaca, N.Y., 1989). Stephen D. White, Custom, Kinship, and Gifts to Saints: The Laudatio Parentum in Western France, 1050-1150 (Chapel Hill, N.C., 1988).

3. A. Germain, ed., Liber instrumentorum memorialium: Cartulaire des Guillems de Montpellier (Montpellier, 1884), nos. 402 ff.

4. Ibid, nos. 484, 485, 490, 491, 500, 501-3.

5. To appear in Law and History Review (1997).

6. See for examples the cases printed in P.C. Timbal, ed., La Guerre de Cent Ans vue á travers les registres du Parlement de Paris (Paris, 1961), and for ecclesistical affairs my Ph.D. thesis, "The Judicial Origins of Parlementary Gallicanism" (Harvard University, 1959); for the theoretical context see my "Choice of Law in Medieval France," in Essays in Legal History in Honor of Justice Felix Frankfurter, ed. M. Forkosch (Indianapolis, 1966), pp. 481-96.

This review is reproduced here from Speculum 71 (1996), 998-1006 by kind permission of Professor Cheyette]

 


Paul R. Hyams

Susan Reynolds, Fiefs & Vassals: the Medieval Evidence Reinterpreted (New York : Oxford University Press, 1994). Pp. xi + 544. $39.95 (0-19-820458-2).

The development of the social and political structures out of which emerged the modern European state was a long protracted process, the early stages of which are sparsely documented to say the least. The received view has long been that military arrangements were fundamental during the western middle ages, that they determined the shape of much else and - some say -- fixed the eventual form of the nascent state. This is all very plausible. Models constructed on this premise have proved immensely helpful to both the narratives expected of nineteenth-century historians and the analyses of their more recent successors.

Though "Feudalism" is emphatically not a term native to the medieval period, words like feodum (translated or frenchified as "fief") continue to satisfy most scholars as adequate warrant for a feudal vocabulary of words and concepts. This usage has greatly facilitated comparisons between one region and another. England was not feudalized until 1066, some say, much later than France. Parts of the Netherlands and central Europe escaped altogether. "This" is a pre-feudal survival; "that", when properly understood, a post-feudal feature in advance of its time, and so on. The model has proved even more indispensible to those whose interest lay in the comparison of whole societies and cultures, sociologists as much as historians. Feudalisms have been found and, supposedly, measured against each other the world over. The Islamic iqta and the Japanese chigyo were each enhanced in its own way by receipt of the feudal accolade.

And men looked and they found it good. All this represents a huge investment of intellectual time and effort, not to mention a great deal of intelligence and insight. Little wonder then that most scholars are highly loath to abandon any part of it. Yet the drawbacks, as in "The Emperor's New Clothes", were always evident to any outside viewer with an open mind. Hardly any two writers agreed in their understanding of the model, even when they said they did, or when they explicitly used a predecessor's definition. Those who took the trouble to frame a precise definition always slid away from it once they entered in medias res, as it were. Where good models enhance the data's meaning (or are dropped), the Feudalism model exhibited all the warning signs of counter-productivity. Evidence that failed to fit tended to get shunted aside as an anomaly, pre-, post- or extra-feudal as required. Thus failures seldom got to modify and sharpen the main model. It seemed to some users as if the word "feudal" alone was enough to render comprehensible phenomena they could not otherwise explain in direct language. Feudalism served all too often as a semantic smokescreen.

In the aftermath of British scandals around the multiple use of a very different kind of model in the 1960s, one great scholar foreswore the use of all models in the future. This would be an over-reaction here. We know these days that we could not avoid models if we tried. Better by far to make conscious than ignorant use of them. For scholars they inevitably remain an essential tool of social description and analysis, not least those of past societies. Still, the case for a fifty-year moratorium on the use of the "F"-word and its derivatives does look unanswerable. Plenty of smaller-scale images and models exist to fill any feared lacuna. Most of these serve much better to prompt us to pose direct questions at our sources, questions which are in principle answerable and lead to advances in the genuine understanding of ther men and women of the past and the patterns within which they led their lives. In pursuing my own researches along these lines, I have had much company at least since Peggy Brown's notorious article on "Feudalism: the Tyranny of a Concept" in 1974.1 Meanwhile, the majority of academic historians and much of the rest of the learned world remain frightened of change. Very few dare compose textbooks without the assistance of a calming dollop of the Feudalism drug. Our students feed on lies that they can easily grasp, in place of harder because more complex truths. This should matter to all save the most deeply lost of post-modernists. In betraying our duty to teach messy complexities, historians make their distinctive contribution to the current predominance of pseudo-analysis and sound-bite.

Susan Reynolds sets out to tackle the nonsense head on. Her book divides analytically into two parts. First she sets up for criticism a model of Feudalism as it is generally understood by scholars. This is no simple task because of the nature of the beast, and many of the usual culprits have already cried "Foul!", claiming that "their" Feudalism is not there. I shall concentrate on this explosive or negative side of the arguments here. That this kind of counter-claim is ultimately unanswerable because unverifiable is in effect part of her critique. She has nevertheless tried to meet it in advance with careful definitions and exclusions.

"This book is concerned only with Feudalism in its supposedly more precise sense", she says, "Its object is to establish how far vassalage and the fief … constituted institutions, comprehensible and helpful (and it concludes that) inso far as they are definable and comprehensible, they are not helpful."

But she also tries to suggest how to proceed in the absence of a Feudalism model, proposing her own questions and hypotheses rather than any new global counter-model. Physically, the book also divides into two parts. The first three chapters examine the generalities, and specifically the two alleged institutions of her title, Fiefs and Vassals. The rest of the book seeks to prove her case country by country, with the bulk (3 chapters) understandably devoted to France but chapters too on Italy (cast in a quite central role), Germany and England.

Before she can criticize the ever-changing myth of Feudalism, she must first construct a single received view. This foolhardy enterprize boils down in the end to the contention that "the relationship between rulers and nobles in the late middle ages had evolved out of that between early medieval war-leaders and their followers" (475). Behind the European state, in other words, should lie the heroic Gefolgschaft. For this she finds no good supporting evidence. Her quest and her corrosive demolition of proof-texts deployed in its defence ranges far and wide. But her main charge attacks the central redoubt of her title, Fiefs and Vassals, from whose institutional fusion many have undoubtedly deduced an honorable, personal dyadic relationship of dependency, sealed by a land grant as guarantee of the allegedly all-important future military support of tenant to lord. She shows convincingly that the contemporary terms behind these analytical categories of fief and vassal did not in the early middle ages carry the meanings the model associates with them. They were not, indeed, the words used for the phenomena at all in key areas and periods. Before 1200, latin "feodum" and equivalents seldom denoted noble property, and probably carried no implication of tenure conditional upon military service. "Nobles and free men did not generally owe military service before the twelfth century because of the grant of anything like fiefs" (477). Latin "vassallus", the "driving force … in the history of feudalism" was largely used around kings to denote royal servants, it was very largely absent from France and Germany in the crucial sub-Carolingian period (10th through 12th cents.) though not (note) from Italy. Neither word denoted anything characteristically noble before the thirteenth century; much of their usage was at a "blue-collar" level of ministerials and border-line freemen. She is sceptical too that there existed in this period any unified ritual of Homage and Fealty. "Human beings use their hands a lot and use them in different ways" (29). Fealty, a high medieval lawyers' Frenching of latin "faith" words, she rightly rejects outright. She prefers to talk in more neutral terms of fidelity oaths (87 sq. etc.), noting that early on they were taken as much and as prominently to kings as to any private lord, hence my own teaching translation of loyalty oath. On this basis, no responsible text-book can call "fealty" an institution before the late twelfth century, or, under that name, after.

Yet in the later middle ages, fief and vassal were conceptualized and did approximate to institutions around which important sectors of society were organized. In her attempt to outline how this came about, Reynolds also explains how both the "feudal" model first surfaced and how it appeared eventually to justify very large-scale characterization of medieval culture as essentially "feudal". While these changes occurred in "a very long twelfth century" (482), the critical period began with the disintegration of Carolingian central power in the tenth and eleventh centuries and culminated in the watershed of Gregorian Reform. The twelfth-century intellectual revival, centered on the schools of Northern France and Italy, went along with new forms of bureaucratic government and a new, much more professional law. The schoolmen publicized new "methods of argument and habits of close attention to the words of texts" (73) that encouraged everywhere an unpacking of concepts previously permitted to clump together unanalyzed. Rights of government and property were now in consequence expounded in a new, much sharper fashion.

Italian lawschools applied the new learning even more directly to social analysis for specifically Italian reasons. They associated recent treatises from their own Lombardy with the prestigious texts of Roman Law as the Libri Feudorum for use in lecture-room and court. Much of their argument on this corpus of material was recorded in writing, and it was here that words like "vassallus" and "feodum" were first defined as feudal terms of art, "a virtually new category" within a systematized conceptualization. For this "process … by which new methods of government and new kinds of legal argument imposed more regular obligations on all property" (69), the "nearest precedents", interestingly enough, "are practices that great churches adopted for dealing with their property" (477). Only now, mostly from the early thirteenth century on, did secular usage in northern Europe progressively adopt the sharper academic terminology, thus laying a foundation on which secular lawyers could erect each in his own country the related analytical systems of the later middle ages. It remained only for sixteenth-century French political theorists and then later historians and antiquarians to read their history of the middle ages backwards through the lenses created by the Lombard lawyers, and hey presto! you have "feudalism" pretty much as we know it today.

As my quotations show, Reynolds is unabashedly empiricist in tone and style. Yet beneath the surface she deploys wide if individual reading in the literature of social theory. At her best, she can render its sporadic opacity into form immediately usable by the most implacably anti-theory archival historian. Thus from much French discussion of signifiers and the signified, she derives her naïve-sounding but serviceable distinction between words, concepts and things. Her target is the tendency to read history backwards from the high middle ages with its fuller evidence and sophisticated systems of legal explication. She rightly doubts that the early middle ages thought in such terms. She also establishes, in plausible style, that the feudo-vassalic hypothesis will not wash; fiefs and vassals were simply neither ubiquitous enough nor, before the thirteenth century, central enough to property and power relations in Western Europe to warrant the focus on them. She is therefore an atheist, not an agnostic, on Feudalism. The thrust of her book is to throw the onus on those who disagree to ask why they still find the creaking model useful. Its defenders should put up or shut up.

This combative stance and the tone in which it is couched are not well calculated to win the hearts and minds of defectors, least of the conservative scholars from Continental Europe from whom many Americans still take their lead. The book reads as almost caricature British, its author the very model of a British revisionist. There is much understatement and honesty discourse. Reynolds admits that her inquiries have been in various respects "unsystematic", "impressionistic", but "I have tried to do my honest best". She sometimes appears to argue against received views simply because these are received.; she would probably call this "testing" them. This is in part a consequence of the task she set herself. To refute the model, she must abstract from it refutable postulates, which the proponents of the theory then deny as theirs. This aridity is likely to have a long run. The defenders' will to resist is strengthened by what they see as her fussiness with words. Reynolds is the last of the nominalists, from whom few accepted meanings are safe. She shares too with this reviewer the delusion that an Oxford tutor (she was for many years an excellent one) can safely differ from the experts in a field by "getting up" the secondary literature and sampling sources from the footnotes. The experts in question are unlikely to take this kindly even or especially when the Oxfordian has got it right. Inevitably, too, area specialists will find errors in her treatment of their patches. All one can say is that the Europeans ought to read the book carefully rather than reject its findings with horror in advance.

This is, then, an important and courageous book of considerable achievements, which will in time influence radical changes of approach and interpretation. No scholar can be forgiven in future for confusing modern models with those used by contemporaries and deucible from strictly contemporary medieval materials alone. Reynolds has gone far to establish and contextualize the impact of schools discussions on late medieval perceptions of their society and socio-political culture. One can equally applaud the intelligent effort to surmount other artificial barriers of the existing national literatures. Behind the Feudalism model, there undoubtedly lie behavior patterns radiating out from the Frankish heartland that were in some cases eventually known and practised all over Europe. If we accept, as I believe we must, that most text-book models of feudo-vassalic relations are anachronistic and misleading, we rise free of the constraints able to frame newer formulations to facilitate both the better undrstanding of the ways in which Europe functioned as a single culture and to promote comparison with other, more remote regions and different times. This is not the death of cultural comparison, as critics assert, but the opportunity to place comparison on a far safer foundation. For those social historians of kingship, lordship and power relations who take heed of Reynolds' message, Fiefs and Vassals should mark a real watershed.

On legal matters, Reynolds is patently less fully comfortable. Ever impatient with the tangled knots of lawyers' discourse, she would like to reveal the impact of simpler underlying verities on her general themes. This excellent aspiration is, alas, very hard to achieve. Which is more of a pity than it may sound, since so much of the evidence, including the distortions behind the feudal model itself, proceed from "legal" documents and discourse. It is not even as simple as it seems to participate in the arguments of legal scholars expressed in their own technical vocabulary. The crying need for better communications between legal and social scholars remains. Medieval historians are just as much in need as others;. We too are prone to under-estimate the subtleties of lawyers' rule talk, for example. We too tend to underestimate the role of case-specific and non-legislative concerns, such as those of advocates for their clients or of judges forced to deal with political issues. And we too often see strict rules in "legal" sources where lawyers think more in terms of Dworkinian principles that wax and wane in strength according to the changing preferences of disputants and courts for one norm or another.

Lawyers will undoubtedly feel too that Reynolds fails to appreciate all such bread-and-butter distinctions. Her common-sense notion of "full property" is quite central to much of her argument. But property and ownership are highly complex notions, involving in most societies various levels of interest. Some kind of opposition is implied when Reynolds discusses less than full rights in land and ejections from holdings. Yet neither the "possession" of Roman law and later medieval secular laws or early medieval "seizin" figures in the index, or to any serious degree in the argument. She simply cannot be telling the whole story.

Lawyers also habitually distinguish mere de facto succession to property and office from full rights to inherit, between succession and heritability. Hence their scepticism (so frustrating for the historian) about rights existing without corresponding legal remedies. Reynolds holds, as I do, that one may talk about rights before the birth of the Common Law and similar systems, but does not seem to understand why lawyers fail to share her viewpoint or why a Brian Tierney, for example, talks of a twelfth-century invention of rights as so revolutionary a change. In the end, this may strengthen her general case, as John Hudson has recently hinted in a thoughtful study of property concepts in twelfth- and early thirteenth-century England. But it greatly weakens the plausibility of her recurring treatment of property rights in the body of the book.

But enough carping. The final judgement must be congratulatory. This book largely disposes of the ancient myth that feudo-vassalic relations characterized the medieval West. It is true that such practised shape-changers may long survive in one manifestation or another. And non-historians, social scientists in particular, will undoubtedly hang on to their feudal constructs and ideal types. Still, a new generation of historians will surely now see (literally) through the specter. And one can hope that social and political scientists will at least desist from their misuse of medieval Europe to validate their doubtless well-conceived models. Susan Reynold's account of the establishment of the myth and her suggestions of how to live life without it are always interesting and often persuasive. They certainly deserve to gain respect even where they may fail to command general acceptance. Reynolds and we can ask no more than that scholars will scrutinize her contentions in the same generous and critical spirit as she has written this fine book.

PAUL R. HYAMS,
HISTORY DEPARTMENT, CORNELL.

An edited version of this review was published in Journal of Interdisciplinary History (1997), 00-00 as "The End of Feudalism?"


Source.

http://falcon.arts.cornell.edu/~prh3/427/texts/feudalism.html

© Translation by Paul Hyams of Cornell University. See his home page/copyright page. Prof   Hyams indicates that the translations are available for educational use. He intends to expand the number of translations, so keep a note of his home page. 


This text is part of the Internet Medieval Source Book. The Sourcebook is a collection of public domain and copy-permitted texts related to medieval and Byzantine history.

Unless otherwise indicated the specific electronic form of the document is copyright. Permission is granted for electronic copying, distribution in print form for educational purposes and personal use. If you do reduplicate the document, indicate the source. No permission is granted for commercial use.

Paul Halsall, July 1998
[email protected]



The Internet History Sourcebooks Project is located at the History Department of  Fordham University, New York. The Internet Medieval Sourcebook, and other medieval components of the project, are located at the Fordham University Center for Medieval Studies.The IHSP recognizes the contribution of Fordham University, the Fordham University History Department, and the Fordham Center for Medieval Studies in providing web space and server support for the project. The IHSP is a project independent of Fordham University.  Although the IHSP seeks to follow all applicable copyright law, Fordham University is not the institutional owner, and is not liable as the result of any legal action.

© Site Concept and Design: Paul Halsall created 26 Jan 1996: latest revision 12 April 2024 [CV]